consequences of our actions? Our ability to measure and to predict the benefits and

harms resulting from a course of action or a moral rule is dubious, to say the least.

Perhaps the greatest difficulty with utilitarianism is that it fails to take into

account considerations of justice. We can imagine instances where a certain course

of action would produce great benefits for society, but they would be clearly unjust.

South African whites, for example, sometimes claim that all South Africans--

including blacks--are better off under white rule. They have claimed that in those

African nations that have traded a whites-only government for a black or mixed

one, social conditions have rapidly deteriorated. Civil wars, economic decline,

famine, and unrest, they predict, will be the result of allowing the black majority of

South Africa to run the government. If such a prediction is true, then the white

government of South Africa would be morally justified by utilitarianism, in spite of

its injustice.

If our moral decisions are to take into account considerations of justice, then

apparently utilitarianism cannot be the sole principle guiding our decisions. It can,

however, play a role in these decisions. The principle of utilitarianism invites us to

consider the immediate and the less immediate consequences of our actions. It also

asks us to look beyond self-interest to consider impartially the interests of all

persons affected by our actions.

Dewey said, "A class of experts is inevitably so removed from common

interests as to become a class with private interests and private knowledge, which in

social matters is not knowledge at all." Dewey’stheme is that privilege inevitably

produces cognitive distortion: "All special privilege narrows the outlook of those

who possess it, as well as limits the development of those not having it. A very

considerable portion of what is regarded as the inherent selfishness of mankind is

the product of an inequitable distribution of power-inequitable because it shuts out

Page 3

some from the conditions which direct and evoke their capacities, while it produces

a one-sided growth in those who have privilege" (Dewey & Tufts, Ethics, pp. 358-

386).

Dewey's view is that we don't know what our interests and needs are or what

we are capable of until we actually engage in politics. A corollary of this view is that

there can be no final answer to the question of how we should live, and therefore

we should always leave it open to further discussion and experimentation. That is

precisely why we need democracy.

At the same time, we do know that certain things stunt our nature and

capacities. Dewey was well aware that equality and freedom can conflict, and that

there is no easy solution when they do conflict; but he would, I think, feel that this

conflict is too much emphasized in present-day political philosophy. In Dewey's

view, there is simply no doubt that inequality, on the scale that exists today, stunts

our nature and capacities, and thus leads to unfreedom on a massive scale. If we are

to talk about "conflicts between equality and freedom", we should also talk about the

ways in which inequality leads to unfreedom.

In Democracy and Education, Dewey said, “The development within the

young of the attitudes and dispositions necessary to the continuous and progressive

life of a society cannot take place by direct conveyance of beliefs, emotions, and

knowledge. An aim denotes the result of any natural process brought to

consciousness and made a factor in determiningpresent observation and choice of

ways of acting. It signifies that an activity has become intelligent. Specifically it

means foresight of the alternative consequences attendant upon acting in a given

situation in different ways, and the use of what is anticipated to direct observation

and experiment.”

In setting aims for education, Dewey’s emphasis is on freer and better

Page 4

balanced activities--it is a limit set to activity. A utilitarian goal is fixed and rigid. It

aims to imposed upon the process a notion of preparation for a remote future and

renders the work of both teacher and pupil mechanical and slavish. The Deweian

aim is opposed at every point to an aim which is imposed from without. Dictated

orders to do such and such is not a stimulus to intelligence. To consider the

curriculum in its entirety as a kind of composite made by the aggregation of

segregated values can result in a tendency to assign separate values to each study,

and in the isolation of social groups and classes. Dewey fought against these kind of

goals, and considered it the business of education in a democracy to struggle against

this isolation in order that the various interests may reinforce and play into one

another.

I agree with Nodings, “... much of school curriculum should be organized

around themes of care: caring for self, caring for intimate others, caring for strangers

and global others, caring for plants, animals, and the natural environment, caring

for the human-made environment, and caring for ideas.” There is nothing in any

subject itself that is inherently “good for the mind.” Intelligence should be applied

to doing, not to some unseen and stable capacity.

As my society struggles with its exit from an industrial (post-modern) society

while at the same time struggles with its entrance into an information society, I

must side with Dewey, “Since education is the process through which the needed

transformation may be accomplished and not remain a mere hypothesis as to what

is desirable, we reach a justification of the statement that philosophy is the theory of

education as a deliberately conducted practice.” That “Democratic Communitarians”

is preferable to the utilitarians’ value on consequences. I understand that this is not

an either or choice. Since I cannot know consequences with certainty, I will rely

more heavily on Dewey’s “Democratic Communitarians.”

Page 5